.
VR
shyloc's Journal



THIS JOURNAL IS ON 13 FAVORITE JOURNAL LISTS

Honor: 0    [ Give / Take ]

PROFILE




17 entries this month
 

?????????????

19:34 Nov 21 2005
Times Read: 546


due to a recent read i kinda feel compaild to write, don know whats its going to be about, so it will probly be a waste of your time. it was poetry,beutiful dark hearted poetry.it had words such as scorched,and blackend.sweet, huh.

i thought so..i read all of them,all of witch was

poetry of the lonesom romantic.i liked it so much, i dare not share it.i dont want any numbskull to coment and scew it up.she has a way with the madness that seem to plauge her soul.i feel for those who ake like i do. oh heres anouther qoute i like,, its MR.T's. im sure you will remember it.. he would say. "I pitty the Fool". it was funny then and still is, but only now i can actually relate to it,"sad but true".oh well, nothing come to mind to really write about now..soo i will pass on.


COMMENTS

-



 

random

16:41 Nov 19 2005
Times Read: 552


i awoke to the sound of splashes in the pool. when i got up and went to it,there was noone there.i know i heard something in it.it wasnt a dream was it,no it wasn't.there were wet spots on the walk.small foot prints.my brothern were not home. noone was.could this have been that little sceaming soul that fallows me,the one in witch i thought that i got away from months ago. if it was why wait so long to play with my mind.why was it here now.i had to think back to the last time i saw or even spoke to it.back at ft. bragg it was a silent and very seldom seen.there wasnt anthig troubeling him.a small boy.one of whom i just thought was a lost spirit.and found comfort in my knowing of it.or was it i who found the comfort in it? it could have been a combination of the two.but the more i write and ponder on it..the more clear it had become.the immage of him in my thoughts were clear now.he look as i did as a boy.how was this possiable.i had no younger brother at that time.or did i.i cant bear to think that i did.and how he might have came to pass.should i love him..i have too.only seeing and hearing of him when an elder would, in the sleep or in the mist of being buisy..whats his name.did he have one.i must find out this.i must!


COMMENTS

-



 

meta

00:02 Nov 19 2005
Times Read: 554


When I say that rotation of the Earth is the cause of alternation of day and night, the meaning of it is, according to our scheme, that if I stop the rotation of the Earth, the effect of alternation will disappear. Clearly, I cannot stop the Earth from rotationg, but this does not make the statement less true or useful. When I think of the rotation of the Earth, I actually have in mind a model of the Solar system, where celestial bodies are represented by balls of appropriate (and convenient for my imagination) sizes. In this model I can actually stop the Earth's rotation and see what happens. This is the true meaning of our causal relationship. Since a model of a model is a model, we often do not care to make distinction between our models and our models of models. As required by our epistemology, we explained causal statements as certain models of the world. We might now ask: what about the concept of model itself? Does it not include the idea of causality? The answer is: yes, it does. In the use of models causality is exploited twice. First, whenever we run the machinery of the model, we expect that the switching on of the model produce a definite effect. Second, when we compare our predictions with the reality, we expect them to match. The fact that there are such phenomena as models of the world is, essentially, the same fact as the existence of causality.


COMMENTS

-



 

random

23:58 Nov 18 2005
Times Read: 555


What is meant by the { nature} in this context?'' Indeed, we want to understand clearly the meaning of the question before getting involved in answering.


COMMENTS

-



 

random

22:51 Nov 18 2005
Times Read: 556


why are we here.i dont know. i have begun to think that there is no purpose in life..nothing at all..being born a romantic sucks ass sometime.


COMMENTS

-



 

random

15:03 Nov 18 2005
Times Read: 557


im not sure on what to write but i feel compailed to do so,my thoughts are random today while i try my best not to think of the lessons that are at hand.Trying really hard not to think of them i turn to look at the pictures on the wall."of lee and jackson at the last meating,of napoleon, and socretes,all of witch i have the greatest respect of. there are many more,to many to list.

being a well travled i have a lust for portraits.

I have recently gone for the membership here.i am still awaiting the activation of it.of wich i cant hardly wait. there has never been such an addiction to a web site such as this one i have here.i am thankful that God has given cancer this gift that he has shared with us.i thank both of them.now that i am talking out of my ass i feel a bit dumbfounded..so the time has come to end meaningless babble.


COMMENTS

-



 

cybernetic metaphysic..no i didnt write it..but it is a good read

13:11 Nov 18 2005
Times Read: 559


Philosophy Metaphysics is supposed to answer the question ``What is the nature of things?'', or something like that. Before trying to answer this question we should ask a counterquestion: ``What is meant by the {sl nature} in this context?'' Indeed, we want to understand clearly the meaning of the question before getting involved in answering. In this paper we interpret the metaphysical quest from the vantage point of what we denote as {sl the cybernetic epistemology} ([Tur90]), its main principle being that the meaning of language constructions is defined by the extent to which it can be used as a model of a part of the world, or as a means of constructing such models. Then we present the beginnings of a metaphysics inspired by the cybernetical approach to the world, which is seen in terms of functioning, organization and control, in contrast with the view of the physicist, who features space, time and matter. Starting from these premises we come to a philosophy where ontological priority belongs to {sl action}. A metalanguage is still a language, and a metatheory a theory. Metamathematics is a branch of mathematics. Is metaphysics a branch of physics? `Meta' in Greek means over, and -- since when you jump over something you find yourself behind or after it -- it is also understood as behind and after. The word `metaphysics' is said to originate from the mere fact that the corresponding part of Aristotle's work was positioned right after the part called ``physics''. But it is not unlikely that the term won a ready acceptance as denoting this part of philosophy because it conveyed the purpose of metaphysics, which is to reach beyond the nature ({sl`physis'}) as we perceive it, and to discover the ``true nature'' of things, their ultimate essence and the reason for being. Such a theory would obviously be priceless for judging and constructing more specific physical theories. %This use of the prefix `meta' is somewhat different %from the way we understand it in the 20-th century. A metatheory is a %theory about another theory, which considered as an object of %knowledge: how true it is, how it comes into being, how it is %used, how it can be improved, etc. A metaphysician, in contrast, %would understand his knowledge as a knowledge about the world, %like that of a physicist (scientist, generally), and not as a %knowledge about the scientific theories (which is the realm of %epistemology). If so, metaphysics should take as honorable a place in physics as metamathematics in mathematics. But this is very far from being the case. It would be more accurate to describe the situation as exactly opposite. Popularly (and primarily by the ``working masses'' of scientists and engineers), metaphysics is considered as almost opposite to physics, and utterly useless for it (if not for any reasonable purpose). We shall argue below that this attitude is a hangover from the long outdated forms of empiricism and positivism. A detractor of metaphysics would say that its propositions are mostly unverifiable, if intelligible at all, so it is hardly possible to assign any meaning to them. Thales taught that everything is water. The Pythagoreans taught that everything is number. Hegel taught that everything is a manifestation of the Absolute Spirit. And for Schopenhauer the world is will and representation. All this has nothing to do with science, which allows only precise and verifiable statements. But what does it mean for a statement to be verifiable? According to the naive view on the nature of our language, known as the reflection-correspondence theory, language, like a mirror, creates certain images, reflections of the things around us. But some images can also be arbitrarily fabricated. A statement is true if it corresponds to reality, otherwise it is false. To verify a statement we simply compare it with reality. Any _expression of our language which cannot be immediately interpreted in terms of observable facts, is meaningless and misleading. This viewpoint in its extreme form, according to which all unobservables must be banned from science, was developed by the early nineteenth-century positivism (August Comte). Such a view, however, is unacceptable for science. Even force in Newton's mechanics becomes suspect in this philosophy, because we can neither see nor touch it; we only conclude that it exists by observing the movements of material bodies. Electromagnetic field has still less of the naively understood reality. And the situation with the wave function in quantum mechanics is simply disastrous. The history of the Western philosophy is, to a considerable extent, the history of a struggle against the reflection-correspondence theory. We now consider language as a material to create models of reality. Language works as a whole, and should be evaluated as a whole. It is not necessary that every specific part of it should be put in a direct and simple correspondence with the observable reality. A language and a theory expressed in it are good if they help make correct predictions about the world around us. Human language is a multilevel system. On the lower levels, which are close to our sensual perception, our notions are almost in one-to-one correspondence with some conspicuous elements of perception. In our theories we construct higher levels of language. The concepts of the higher levels do not replace those of the lower levels, as they should if the elements of the language reflected things ``as they really are'', but constitute a new linguistic level, a superstructure over the lower levels. Top-level theories of science are not simply deduced from observable facts; they are constructed by creative acts, and their usefulness can be demonstrated only afterwards. Einstein wrote that foundations of physics are not directly extr acted from experience, but come only by ``free fantasy''. This ``free fantasy'' is the metaphysician's. Democritus, and then Epicurus and Lucretius taught that the world is an empty space with atoms moving around in it. In due time this concept gave birth to classical mechanics and physics, which is, unquestionably, science. At the time of its origin, however, it was as pure a metaphysics as it could be. The existence of atoms was no more verifiable than that of the Absolute Spirit. Physics started as metaphysics. When we understand language as a hierarchical model of reality, i.e. a device which produces predictions, and not as a true static picture of the world, the claim made by metaphysics is read differently. To say that the real nature of the world is such and such means to propose the construction of a model of the world along such and such lines. Metaphysics creates a linguistic structure -- call it a logical structure, or a conceptual framework -- to serve as a basis for further refinements. Metaphysics is the beginning of physics; it provides fetuses for future theories. Even though a mature physical theory fastidiously distinguishes itself from metaphysics by formalizing its basic notions and introducing verifiable criteria, metaphysics, in a very important sense, {sl is physics}. When Thales said that all is water, he did not mean that quite literally; he surely was not that stupid. His `water' should rather be translated as `fluid', some abstract substance which can change its form and is infinitely divisible. The exact meaning of his teaching is then: it is possible to create a reasonable model of the world where such a fluid is the building material. Is not the theory of electromagnetism a refinement of this idea? As for the Pythagoreans, the translation of the statement ``everything is number'' is that it is possible to have a numerical model of the Universe and everything in it. Is not the modern physics such a model? Building intelligent machines is similar to buiding physical theories. Such machines must be able to create and use models of the world around them. Inescapably, we turn to our own intelligence as a model for artificial intelligence. But our brain is a huge and very complicated system. We do not yet know it works and cannot mimic its operation. What we usually do is take the description of the world in terms of our natural language as the primary reality of which our intelligent machines should construct models. The problem is that this reality is not, actually, primary. It is a hodge-podge of the products of brainwork which have been shaped on various occasions and at different times in the process of biological evolution. It is impossible to achieve good results on this basis as long as we cannot imitate the brain processes in their totality. What we should do is imitate the development of the brain, the way it has evolved, and not the complex system it has become now. We must copy only the principles, but apply them to some new fresh-made concepts implemented in the material which we know how to work with -- unlike the actual nerve nets of the human brain. We must take some most primary, basic elements of the world and conctruct artificial intelligence on this basis. It is metaphysics that can direct us toward these most primary elements, as well as the right ways to operate with them. The meaning of metaphysics is in its potential. I can say that Hegel's Absolute Spirit is meaningless for me, because at the moment I do not see any way how an exact theory can be constructed on this basis. But I cannot say that it is meaningless, period. To say that, I would have to prove that nobody will ever be able to translate this concept into a valid scientific theory, and I, obviously, cannot do that. It may take quite a time to translate metaphysics into an exact theory with verifiable predictions, or a new series of intelligent machines. Before this is done, metaphysics is, like any fetus, highly vulnerable. The task of the metaphysician is hard indeed: he creates his theory in advance of its confirmation. He works in the dark. He has to guess, to select, without having a criterion for selection. Successes on this path are veritable feats of human creativity.
ode{From Kant to Schopenhauer} % part-of: Metaphysics That sensation is the main, and maybe the only, source of our knowledge was noticed already by the ancient Greeks. In the new time, Berkley and Hume stressed this in a very strong manner: things {sl are} our sensations. But rationalists still believed that some crucial ideas are inborn and have nothing to do with the imperfection of our sense organs. Kant synthesized empiricism and rationalism by seeing knowledge as organization of sensations by our mind. Space, time, and other categories are not given us in sensation. They are our forms of perception, the way we organize sensations. This is how {sl synthetic judgments a priory} become possible. They reveal the working methods of our mind which are inborn and do not depend on sensations. In the light of cybernetics, Kant's ideas are surprisingly modern. We say that sensations are at the input of our cognitive apparatus, the nervous system. This input is then processed by a huge hierarchical system. As the signals move up in the hierarchy, sensations become perceptions (there are no sharp boundaries, of course). Mach and Einstein would be, probably, impossible without Kant. They used the Kantian principle of separating elementary facts of sensations and organizing these facts into a conceptual scheme. Einstein's analysis went further from the intuitive space-time picture given by classical mechanics down to the level of separate measurements, and resulted in reorganization of measurements into a different space, the four-dimensional space-time of the relativity theory. This space-time is now as counterintuitive as it was in 1905, even though we have accustomed to it. Hence what we call the paradoxes of the relativity theory. But they do not bother us. We use a bit less of neuronal models, and a bit more of symbolic models, that is all. In quantum mechanics, the physicists went even further. They rejected the idea of a material body located in the space and time as the ultimate reality. The space-time continuum is left as a mathematical construct, and this construct serves the purposes of relating micro-phenomena with macro-phenomena, where it has the familiar classical interpretation. But elementary particles lost their tangible character. In the relativity theory, observations (measurements) at least belong to the same universe as the basic conceptual scheme: the space-time continuum. In quantum mechanics, on the contrary, there is a gap between micro-world and macro-world, between what we believe {sl to really exist}, i.e. quantum particles and fields, and what we take as the basic observable phenomena, which are all expressed in macroscopical concepts: space, time and causality. Here we face the most intriguing part of metaphysics: the concept of `real existence'. Cybernetic epistemology, according to which all meaningful statements are hierarchical models of reality, has a double effect on the concept of existence. On the one hand, theoretical concepts, such as mechanical forces, electromagnetic and other fields, and wave functions, acquire the same existential status as the material things we see around us. On the other hand, quite simple and trustworthy concepts like a heavy mass moving along a trajectory, and even the material things themselves, the egg we eat at breakfast, become as unstable and hazy as theoretical concepts. One can argue that since every theory, in the last analysis explains and organizes observable facts, which all are, and will always be, macroscopic facts, there is simply no need in the concept of real, or ultimate, existence. This is formally true. But we still feel a need for our theory to give an answer to the question of ultimate existence. What is the ultimate reality of physics? This question is not meaningless. Its meaning is in the quest for a theory which would start with concepts bel ieved to correspond to that ultimate reality, and then step by step construct observables from these ``really existing'' things. Somehow it seems that such a theory has better chances for success. If we have a theory of that kind, and it constructs the world from some things --- call them `ex-why-zeds' --- and the theory is born out by experiment, then we can say that the ex-why-zeds {sl do really exist}, and that the world really consists of ex-why-zeds. Ontologically, this will be as certain as when we say that the apple is in a bowl on the basis of seeing it and touching it. The contemporary quantum mechanics does not meet this requirement. It starts with space-time continuum, which in no sense exists. It is only a form of our perception. Suppose we are determined to construct a theory which is built as required above. How should we go about the construction of such a theory? We must go further down in the hierarchy of neuronal concepts. Space and time must not be put in the basis of the theory. They must be constructed and explained in terms of really existing things. An attempt must be made to identify the most essential, pervasive, primordial elements of experience. Kant's metaphysics had served as the philosophical basis for the modern theories of physics. We see now that a further movement down is required. Thus let us turn to the development of metaphysics after Kant. Kant introduced the concept of the thing-in-itself for that which will be left of a thing if we take away everything that we can learn about it through our sensations. Thus the thing-in- itself has only one property: to exist independently of the cognizant subject. This concept is essentially negative; Kant did not relate it to any kind or any part of human experience. This was done by Schopenhauer. To the question `what is the thing-in- itself?' he gave a clear and precise answer: it is {sl will}. The more one thinks about this answer, the more it looks as a revelation. My will is something I know from within. It is part of my experience. Yet it is absolutely inaccessible to anybody except myself. Any external observer will know about myself whatever he can know through his sense organs. Even if he can read my thoughts and intentions -- literally, by deciphering brain signals -- he will not perceive my will. He can conclude about the existence of my will by analogy with his own. He can bend and crush my will through my body, he can kill it by killing me, but he cannot in any way perceive my will. And still my will exists. It is a thing-in-itself. What is then therest of the world as we know it? Schopenhauer answers: a `Vorstellung'. This word was first translated into English as an `idea', and then a `representation'. Both translations are not very precise. In the Russian language we have a word for it which is a literal translation of the German `Vorstellung': `predstavleniye'. `Vorstellung' is something that is put in front of you. It is a world picture we create ourselves -- and put in front of us, so that to some extent it screens the real world. This aspect of Vorstellung is not properly reflected either in `idea' or in `representation'. Schopenhauer's formula for all that exists is: [Exists][Exists] the world = will + representation [Exists][Exists] eon
ode{Will} % part-of: Metaphysics In our thought and language we distinguish two different classes of elements about which we say that they exist: those expressing what we know, or think we know, and those expressing what we are striving for and intend to do. We unite the elements of the first class to referred as {sl knowledge}, and the elements of the second class as {sl will}. They are not isolated from each other. Our goals and even our wishes depend on what we know about our environment. Yet they are not determined by it in a unique way. We clearly distinguish between the range of options we have and the actual act of choosing between them. As an American philosopher noticed, no matter how carefully you examine the schedule of trains, you will not find there an indication as to where you want to go. Another way to describe the relation between will and knowledge is as a dichotomy between `I' and `not-I', or between subject and object. The border between them is defined by the phrase `I can'. Indeed, the content of my knowledge is independednt of my will in the sense that I cannot change it by simply having some intentions or preferences. On the contrary, I can change my intentions without any externally observable actions. I call it my will. It is the essense of my `I'. It is only {sl my} will, i.e. the will of the subject of knowledge, that exists as will. {sl Its} will, and {sl their} wills, if they exist (of course, they do), exist only as my representations. If Kant's view of knowledge has a clear cybernetic interpretation, then even more so has Schopenhauer's view of the world. His formula is borne out by the practice of cyberneticians during the last decades. We try to understand ourselves by building cybernetic creatures and computer programs which model intelligent behaviour. Our artificial models of intellect consist of two parts: a device that collects, stores and processes information; and a decision maker -- another device that keeps certain goals and makes choices in order to reach these goals, using the information from the first device. Thinking about ourselves in those terms we speak about knowledge and will. It is there, and there is nothing beyond it. eon
ode{Freedom} % part-of Metaphysics The concept of will assumes the existence of {sl freedom} to exercise the will. Thus recognizing will as a cornerstone of being, we do the same for freedom. For the mechanistic worldview of the nineteenth century freedom was a misconcept, a nuisence which escaped satisfactory definition within the scientific context. For us freedom is the very essence of the things, and, first of all, of the human person. However, in many minds, science is still associated with the deterministic picture of the world, as it was in the nineteenth century. This picture, was as follows. Very small particles of matter move about in virtually empty three-dimensional space. These particles act on one another with forces which are uniquely determined by their positioning and, possibly, velocities.The forces of interaction, in their turn, uniquely determine, in accordance with Newton's laws, the subsequent movement of particles. Thus each subsequent state of the world is determined, in a unique way, by its preceding state. Determinism was an intrinsic feature of the scientific worldview of that time. In such a world there was no room for freedom: it was illusory. Humans, themselves merely aggregates of particles, had as much freedom as wound-up watch mechanisms. In the twentieth century the scientific worldview has undergone a radical change. It has turned out that subatomic physics cannot be understood within the framework of the naive realism of the nineteenth century scientists. The theory of relativity and, especially, quantum mechanics require that our worldview be based on critical philosophy, according to which all our theories and mental pictures of the world are only devices to organize and foresee our experience, and not the images of the world as it ``really'' is. Thus along with the twentieth-century's specific discoveries in the physics of the microworld, we must regard the inevitability of critical philosophy as a scientific discovery -- one of the greatest of the twentieth century. We now know that the notion that the world is ``really'' space in which small particles move along definite trajectories, is illusory: it is contradicted by experimental facts. We also know that determinism, i.e. the notion that in the last analysis all the events in the world must have specific causes, is illusory too. On the contrary, freedom, which was banned from the science of the nineteenth century as an illusion, became a part, if not the essence, of reality. There is genuine freedom in the world. When we observe it from the outside, it takes the form of quantum-mechanical unpredictability; when we observe it from w ithin, we call it our free will. We know that the reason why our behaviour is unpredictable from the outside is that we have ultimate freedom of choice. This freedom is the very essence of our personalities, the treasure of our lives. It is given us as the first element of the world we come into. Logically, the concept of free will is primary, impossible to derive or to explain from anything else. The concept of necessity, including the concept of a natural law, is a derivative: we call necessary, or predetermined, those things which cannot be changed at will. eon
ode{Action} % part-of: Metaphysics line{sf hfill Am Anfang war die Tat.} line{ hfill {it Goethe}.} smallskip Will is manifested in {sl action}. Will and action are inseparable. Our understanding of will is this: will is not a description of options the subject has, nor is it a list of preferences of the subject -- these are all representations; will is the quality that allows to choose between the (possible) options and act. Action and will are two faces of essentially the same phenomenon, and in the philosophy we are developing, action is its perceivable part. A human subject that performs an action usually sees it from within as an action of his will. But not every action, of course, is an action of a human subject; we regard them as manifestations of some other, non-human, wills. We rewrite Schopenhauer's formula as follows: [Exists][Exists] the world = action + representation [Exists][Exists] If we are looking for the ultimate undoubted reality, we must turn to action, and not to the space-time picture of the world. For a picture is only a picture, a representation which changes from one subject to another, from one theory to another; while action is an irrefutable reality. Our knowledge of anything in the world starts with sensations. Sensations are not things. They do not have reality as things. Their reality is that of an event, an action. Sensation is an {sl interaction} between the subject and the object, a physical phenomenon. Consider the concept of action in the context of physics. According to our present understanding of the world, all the variety of events we observe result from elementary acts of interaction between elementary particles. These acts constitute unquestionable reality, while both our theory, and our intuitive picture of the world, are only representations of reality. Furthermore, it is the physical quantity of {sl action} that is quantized by Plank's constant [Exists]h[Exists]. This can be seen as an indication that action should have a higher existential status than space, time, or matter. Of course, it is not immediately clear whether the concept of action as we understand it intuitively and the physical quantity that has the dimension of energy by time and called `action' are one and the same, or related at all. That the physicists use the word `action' to denote this quantity could be a misleading coincidence. Yet the intuitive notion of an action as proportional to the intensity (intuitive understanding of energy) and the time does not seem unreasonable. Furthermore, it is operators, i.e., {sl actions} in the space of states, that represent observable (real!) physical quantities in quantum mechanics, and not the space-time states themselves! Even if we reject these parallels and intuition as unsafe, it still remains true that neither space, nor time, nor matter are characterized by a single constant indestructible quantum, but a combination of these. Is it not natural to take this combination as a basis for the picture of the world --- if not for a unifying physical theory? The purpose of metaphysics is to find in our experience the most fundamental elements or aspects of the world. We take actions as such, which means that in the model of the world we are constructing the lowest level of representations consists of representations of actions.
ode{Action ontology} % part-of: Action Action and event are prominent features of reality, so philosophers explored them since very long. The idea that events may be, in some sense, more primary than space and time has been appearing, now and then. Russell, in his treatment of time and space, takes ``as raw material'' events, quote{ which are to be imagined as each occupying a finite continuous portion of space-time. It is assumed that two events can overlap, and that no event recurs.} The motive is to explain and justify the continuing use by the physicists of instants in time and points in space while rejecting at the same time Newton's conception of absolute time and space, which conferred to instants and points a great deal of ontological primacy. Using events, Russel defines instants as follows: quote{ An `instant' as I propose to define them, is a class of events having the following two properties: (1) all the events in the class overlap; (2) no event outside the class overlaps with every member of the class.} Russel's event is, essentially, a set-theoretic concept. It is a set of instants of time. It remains so even when instant (element) is defined through set (event) as the intersection of a certain family (class) of sets. This class is nothing but the set of all events which include a given instant. Typically for a set-thereticall approach, all these concepts are static, do not really involve action. Action proper is treated by several contemporary philosophers, including Aune, Davidson, Quine, Sellars and others. To quote Bruce Aune [Aun88], quote{ Perhaps the most controversial aspect of so called action theory is its subject matter. This subject matter is generally said to be (or to concern) actions, but different philosophers conceive of actions in radically different ways. For some philosophers, actions are abstract entities -- states of affairs, propositions, sets, or even ordered pairs of some kind. For others, actions are distinctively concrete entities located in space and time. Another group of philosophers, among whome I include myself, have even denied that actions are required for a reasonable action theory, insisting that agents or actors will suffice as the theory's sole objects.} For us, actions are concrete, in the sense that they constitute the primary reality and not man-made representation, such as propositions, sets etc., which are referred in the quote as `abstract entities'. At the same time we cannot say that actions are located in space and time; it is space and time that are constructed from actions. The high ontological status of action which we maintain is usually rejected on the grounds that action is not `fundamental' enough. Thus Aune writes: quote{ According to an agent theory, although agents clearly exist and may truly be described as acting in this or that way, it is philosophically misleading to say that their actions or deeds also exist.} Aune justifies his view-point by using the concept of fundamental realities, which is traced back to Aristotle. A pile of stones is less fundamental than the stones which make it up. If a pile exists at all, then it does so in some weaker form than the stones. We read further in Aune's paper: quote{ Philosophers holding what are known as substance ontologies contend that the fundamental objects of our world are continuants -- and nothing but continuants. A continuant is a thing like a man,a marble, or a tree: something that, as Aristotle said, persists in time and can undergo change. Philosophers holding an agent theory often accept such an ontology. If fundamental objects are continuants, then changes, events, and therefore actions are not fundamental objects; their existence is derivative at best.} Our view is exactly the opposite: actions constitute the reality which we perceive through our sense organs; agents are representations, elements of a language, which we use to construct models explaining the observed actions. This view is {sl action ontolgy}. The reason why we espouse this ontolgy is inseparable from our cybernetic epistemology. We do not take the concept of existence as given intuitively, nor do we think about it as a reflection of `real' existence. For us, fundamental things, i.e. things that have the greatest degree of existence, are those we start with when we construct our models of the world: the cornerstones of construction. To pick up those cornerstones we look for the most certain, unquestionable facts of life, and we find that they are actions (the word {sl fact} itself comes from the Latin {sl facere}, which means to do or to make). Moreover, our knowledge itself, i.e. a collection of the world's models, is nothing but action; the only meaning of a model is in its operation. Representations are arbitrary: a matter of convenience; the changes in representations must correspond to the changes in reality if we want to have a true model. The translational relativity (symmetry) of space is the best illustration of this. When we think of an isolated point, we do not yet think about space. Space is created by certain actions: moves, or shifts. These shifts are a measurable reality. The points in space have meaning only with respect to some reference system. The same shift on a line can be seen as a shift from point 3 to point 7 or from point 12 to 16. The choice of a reference -- i.e. representation -- system is arbitrary. eon
ode{Agent} % part-of: Action When we speak of an action, we speak also of an {sl agent} that performs the action. An agent is the carrier of will, the entity that chooses between possible actions. We do not see agents, we see only what they are doing. But we use the concept of agent to create models of the world. When we speak of actions of human beings we know very well what the agent is: just the person whose action it is. We reconstruct this notion, of course, starting from our own `I'. When we speak of such animals as dogs, we again have no doubt in the validity of the concept {sl agent}. This reasoning can be continued down to frogs, worms, amoebas, trees, and inanimate objects, without any convincing arguments for stopping. When we say: ``the bomb exploded and the ship sank'', are there any reasons to object against understanding this in the same way as if we were speaking abut people and dogs? After all, if the bomb was not very big, the ship might or might not sink, depending on the {sl ship} itself, the ship as a whole. Notice that even given a definite ship and a definite time, the result might not be uniquely predetermined. And what about an {sl act} (sic!) of radioactive decay? It is definitely an action, but whose action is it? The physicist could say that the agents here are electrodynamic and chromodynamic fields. This make sense because of the theory the physicist has. If we do not have such a theory, we simply say that there is a special agent for each possible act of radioctive decay. At each moment in time this agent makes a choice: to decay or not to decay. This immediately explains the exponential law of radioactivity. Introduction of agents is, speaking informally, our first theory of the world. The primary instance of an agent for a human being is itself. So, it is not surprising that in primitive societies the concept of agent is understood anthropomorphically: as something which is very similar, if not identical, to ourselves. Hence the animism of primitive thinking: understanding of all actions as initiated by various kinds of spirits or other imaginary creatures. The development of modern science banned spirits from the picture of the world. But agents, cleared from anthropomorphism, still remain, even though the physicists do not call them so. What is Newtonian force if not an agent that changes, every moment, the momentum of a body? Physics concentrates on the description of the world in space and time; it leaves -- at least at present -- the concept of angent implicit. We need it explicitly because of our metaphysics based on the concept of action, not to mention the simple fact that cybernetics describes, among other things, the behavior of human agents. (This last field of application of cybernetics is, of course, one of the reasons for our metaphysics). eon
ode{Emergence} % part-of: Action Agents come into, and go out of, existence. For centuries philosophers grappled with a problem: how to distinguish simple (``quantitative'') changes from the cases where something really ``new'' emerges. What does it mean to be ``new'', to emerge? In our theory this intuitive notion is formalized as the coming of a new agent into existence. An action can lead to an emergence of new agents. Take radioactive decay. A neutron suddenly {sl chooses} to break down into a proton, electron and neutrino. Whatever agents could have been involved into the events around the neutron do not exist anymore. New agents, such as the interaction between the newborn proton and electron emerge. In the case of complex actions, such as the birth of a baby, we can argue about the exact time of the event, because we have more than one reference system in which to describe actions. As a member of society, the baby emerges at birth. As an object of embryology it emerges at the moment of egg fertilization. eon
ode{Event} % part-of: Action When we ignore the agent, we speak of actions as events. Event is an action abstracted from the agent. eon eon
ode{State} % part-of: Metaphysics The idea of a {sl state} of the world, or some part of the world, is familiar to everybody who took elementary courses in science. It is usually considered so basic that there is no need and, probably, possibility of definition. But we need a definition, because the only undefinable element in our metaphysics is action. Our definition is: a state of a part of the world is the set of actions that are possible in this state, with their probabilities, if this concept is applicable. Two states in which all the same actions are possible and equally probable are the same state, because there is no way to distinguish between them. For example, if the state of affairs is such that there is an apple on the table in front of me, I can reach it and pick it up. If there is no apple this is impossible. If the moon is on the night sky, I can execute the action of observing it. For this purpose I rotate my head in a certain way and keep my eyes open. An atom is in an excited state when it can emit a photon. There are states of a type different from what we have considered above, the states for which our definition is not suitable. If I feel pain, or am frustrated, or elated, angry, or complacent, this has no effect on the actions I can take. It affects only the choices I am going to make selecting from the same set of possible actions. Indeed, if my hand is over a gas heater and hurts (say, gently, for plausibility), I still have the choice between keeping the hand where it is, or withdrawing. But, obviously, the more it hurts, the more likley I am to withdraw it. Thus we come to distinguish between: list a physical state, which is a set of possible actions for the subject of knowledge and other agents; and list a mental state, which influences the choices to be made by the subject, but does not alter the set of possible actions.
i This dichotomy clearly reflects the fundamental feature of the world as consisting of the will and representation. A physical state is that of representation. A mental state is a state of the subject's will. When we use the concept of an agent in out model of the world we may endow agents with some `mental' states. However, such a state remains physical for all other agents: part of the representation of the world. It is only the subject's mental states which belong to the category of will. Other agent's will is for me only a representation. When speaking of ``states'' without any of the two adjectives, we shall mean physical states. We have already had a number of reasons for considering action the most fundamental observable reality. Seeing action in the context of state provides more of it. The concept of state is a strong contender for the most basic role. Indeed, the standard beginning of a theory is to introduce states of the objects of the theory, whatever they are, and then define actions, which are understood as certain changes of the state. But when we define an action as a change of the state, we introduce something new, which is not present in the idea of a state; change is an event i.e. an action abstracted from the agent that performs it. Thus we cannot avoid introducing action as an undefinable element. At the same time the state of the world can be defined through action, as we have just demonstrated. eon
ode{The algebra of actions} % part-of: Metaphysics Algebra is the part of mathematics that deals with operations. Operations are actions. Since action is the basic reality of the world, algebra is the beginning of all beginnings.
ode{Domain} % part-of: The algebra of actions A set of actions is referred to as a {sl domain}. It is a formalization of the idea of `a part of the world'. The models we are given by nature and construct artificially are never universal. They are always applicable only to some part of reality. This part is the domain of the model. Since states of that part of reality are defined by sets of actions, the domain of a model also defines the set of all states which can, in principle, exist: it the powerset (the set of all subsets) of the domain. The actul set of possible states may be a subset of this powerset. When we apply a model (in particular, a theory), we assume that only those actions take place that are within the domain. Make an action which is not included in the domain, and the whole theory may become out of place. The states of the world are defined as subsets of the domain of the model. Other actions are ignored; they may be either irrelevant, when they have no impact on the legitimacy of the model, or prohibited, when they make the model unapplicable. eon
ode{Null action} % part-of: The algebra of actions We call a {sl null action} the absence of any action. An action which is not null is a {sl non-null} action. eon
ode{Composition} % part-of: The algebra of actions There are two ways to unite actions into a composite action. If [Exists]a_1[Exists] and [Exists]a_2[Exists] are actions then their {sl sequential composition}, denoted as [Exists](a_1;a_2)[Exists], or just [Exists]a_1a_2[Exists], is the action which is performed by first performing [Exists]a_1[Exists] and then, immediately, [Exists]a_2[Exists]. We say that action [Exists]a_1[Exists] is {sl sequential part of} action [Exists]a[Exists], if there exists an action [Exists]a_2[Exists] such that [Exists]a_1a_2=a[Exists]. If [Exists]a_1[Exists] and [Exists]a_2[Exists] are actions then their {sl parallel composition}, denoted as or [Exists](a_1parallel a_2)[Exists], is the action which is performed by performing [Exists]a_1[Exists] and [Exists]a_2[Exists] in parallel. We say that action [Exists]a_1[Exists] is {sl parallel part of} action [Exists]a[Exists], if there exists an action [Exists]a_2[Exists] such that [Exists]a_1 parallel a_2=a[Exists].
ode{Process} % part-of: Composition A composite action is referred to as a {sl process}. eon eon
ode{Inverse action} % part-of: The algebra of actions Given an action [Exists]a[Exists], we denote as [Exists]ar{a}[Exists] the action such that [Exists]aar{a}[Exists] and [Exists]ar{a}a[Exists] is an action which returns the world to the same state as before this compsite action. For a given [Exists]a[Exists] the inverse action [Exists]ar{a}[Exists] may or may not exist. If it does exist, [Exists]a[Exists] is {sl reversible}, otherwise {sl irreversible}. eon
ode{Continuous vs. discreet} % part-of: The algebra of actions A {sl domain} is {sl continuous} if for every action [Exists]a[Exists] there exist two actions [Exists]a_1[Exists] and [Exists]a_2[Exists] such that neither is null and the composite action [Exists]a_1a_2[Exists] is the same as [Exists]a[Exists]. Note, that the requirement for [Exists]a_1a_2[Exists] and [Exists]a[Exists] is {sl to be the same}, and not just lead to the same state. An action [Exists]a[Exists] is {sl elementary} if [Exists]a
ot= a_1 a_2[Exists] for any two non-null actions [Exists]a_1[Exists] and [Exists]a_2[Exists]. A domain is {sl discrete} if every action from it can be represented by a finite sequence of elementary actions. A domain may have discrete and continuous subdomains. eon eon
ode{Cognitive action} % part-of: Metaphysics Among the possible actions which constitute a state of the world there are some which are performed by the subject of knowledge with the explicit purpose of increasing the subject's knowledge. We shall call them {sl cognitive actions}. Actually, there is no sharp boundary between purely cognitive actions and other actions which serve different purposes. Each action can be considered cognitive to the extent it takes part in the formation of a model of the world. When I rotate my head to see the moon, this is, obviously, a good cognitive action. To take an apple is to a great extent a cognitive action for a baby who is just now forming the concept of an external object. It is also cognitive for a blind man who has no other way to know that an apple is there. But if you take an apple after you have seen it, this hardly adds much to your mental model of the world. The act is alimentary rather than cognitive. eon
ode{Modeling scheme} %MODEL, part-of: KNOW, Knowledge The basic principle of the cybernetic epistemology is that knowledge is a {sl model} of (a part of) the world. Below we define the concept of a model as it is most commonly used (see Fig.1). {midinsert smallskip egtt{ setbox1 = hbox{[Exists]R[Exists]} wd1 = 0in setbox2 = hbox{[Exists]r_1[Exists]} wd2 = 0in setbox3 = hbox{[Exists]r_2[Exists]} wd3 = 0in setbox4 = hbox{[Exists]M_a[Exists]} wd4=0in setbox5 = hbox{[Exists]w_1[Exists]} wd5=0in setbox6 = hbox{[Exists]w_2[Exists]} wd6=0in setbox7=hbox{[Exists]a[Exists]} wd7=0in ~ ~ ox4 ~ ox2 ox3 ~ -{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-} {f model} ~ | | ~ | | ~ |copy1 |ox1 ~ | ox7 | ~ ox5 | |ox6 ~ -{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-} {f world} ~ endtt} medskip centerline{
m Fig.1. The modeling scheme} endinsert} smallskip A model is a system which includes: (1) a certain subsystem, whose states will be referred to as {sl representations}; (2) a {sl representation procedure} [Exists]R[Exists], such that if performed when the state of the world is [Exists]w[Exists] it causes a certain representation [Exists]r = R(w)[Exists] in the system; (3) a family [Exists]R_a[Exists] of {sl modeling procedures} which depend on a possible action [Exists]a[Exists] in the world and convert one representation into another. For the system to be a (correct) model, the modeling procedures must have the following property. Let the world be in a state [Exists]w_1[Exists], and suppose that system [Exists]S[Exists] makes an action [Exists]a[Exists], as a result of which the state of the world becomes [Exists]w_2[Exists]. Then the modeling procedure [Exists]M_a[Exists] applied to the representation [Exists]r_1 = R(w_1)[Exists] produces the representation [Exists]r_2[Exists] of the resulting state [Exists]w_2[Exists]: [Exists][Exists] M_a(R(w_1)) = r_2 = R(w_2) [Exists][Exists]. Thus by applying [Exists]M_a[Exists] to [Exists]r_1[Exists] the system can predict, to some extent, the development of events in the world resulting from its action [Exists]a[Exists]. This definition describes equally well the case of a dog catching in flight a piece of sugar, and an astronomer who computes the position of a planet in the sky. In the first case, the model is built in the material of nervous cells of the dog's brain, in the second case from the signs that the astronomer writes on paper when he makes computations. Mathematically, a model is defined by the representation function [Exists]R(w)[Exists] and the family of modeling functions [Exists]M_a(r)[Exists], for possible actions [Exists]a[Exists] of the system. When we fix an action [Exists]a[Exists], we have what is known as a {sl homomorphism}. Thus a model is a family of homomorphisms. eon
ode{Observation} % part-of: Metaphysics Observation is an abstraction of knowledge from the impact of our cognitive actions on the world. The state of the world [Exists]w_i[Exists] in Fig.1 and the action of using the procedure [Exists]R[Exists] are not really separable: it is an action of cognition, interaction of the subject and the object. When we speak of observation, we assume that there exist cognitive actions which only serve us to acquire knowledge, but have no influence on the phenomena we observe. For instance, when we watch a party of billiards, the positions of the balls are registered by means of the light thrown on the balls and reflected into our eyes. We rightly believe that the effect of the lighting on the movements of the balls is negligible, so we speak about the play in a complete abstraction from the way we know about it. This separation is not always possible. Quantum mechanics deals with actions so elementary that the means we use to know of them cannot be abstracted from. Our usual ``classic'' notions of space and time include the a bstraction of observation. Indeed, the mental construction of a reference frame uses actions of shifting and waiting (doing nothing) which are assumend to have no effect on the studied processes; for quantum-mechanical processes this assumption is not valid, and the classic space-time frame of reference looses its legitimacy, becomes meaningless. One should not use in mental constructions and experiments the things known not to exist. eon
ode{Objective description of the world} % part-of: Metaphysics By objective description of the world we mean, first, a description in terms of some {sl objects}, and second, a description which is, as much as possible, ``objective'' in the usual sense, i.e. impersonal, not depending on the cognitive actions, or other features, of the subject of knowledge. As we shall see, the use of the same word in these two meanings is not accidental: a description can be ``objective'' because it is a description in terms of objects.
ode{Object} % part-of: Objective description of the world Suppose I am aware of a tea-pot on the table in front of me. This is a result of my having the mechanism of abstraction in the brain. I recognize the image on my retina as belonging to a certain set of images, the abstraction `tea-pot'. But there is more to it. I perceive the tea-pot as an {it object}. The object `tea-pot' is certainly not a definite image on the retina of my eyes; not even a definite part of it. For when I turn my head, or walk around the table, this image changes all the time, but I still perceive the tea-pot as the same object. The tea-pot as an object must, rather, be associated with the transformation of the image on my retina which results from the changing position of my eyes. This is, of course, a purely visual concept. We can add to it a transformation which produces my tactile sensations given the position and movements of my fingers. The general definition of an object suggested by this example consists of three parts. smallskip
i (1) First we define a set [Exists]R_{ob}[Exists] of representations which are said to represent the same object; in our example this set consists of all images of the tea-pot when I look at it from different view-points, and possibly, my sensations of touching and holding it.
i (2) Then from the set of all possible actions we separate a subset [Exists]A_{cogn}[Exists] of actions which will be referred to as {sl cognitive}; in our case [Exists]A_{cogn}[Exists] includes such actions as looking at the tea-pot, turning my head, going around the table, touching the tea-pot etc. -- all those actions which are associated with the registration of the fact that a tea-pot is there.
i (3) Finally, we define a family of functions [Exists]f_a(r)[Exists], where for every cognitive action [Exists]a in A_{cogn}[Exists], the function [Exists][Exists] f_a: R_{ob} o R_{ob} [Exists][Exists]
i transforms a representaiton [Exists]r in R_{ob}[Exists] into [Exists]f_a(r) = r'[Exists] which is expected as a result of action [Exists]a[Exists]. smallskip The most important part here is the third; the first two can be subsumed by it. We define an object [Exists]b[Exists] as a family of functions [Exists]f_a[Exists]: [Exists][Exists] b = {f_a: a o A_{cogn}} [Exists][Exists] The set [Exists]A_{cogn}[Exists] is the domain of the index [Exists]a[Exists]; the set [Exists]R_{ob}[Exists] is the domain and co-domain of the functions of the family. When I perceive an object [Exists]b[Exists], I have a representation [Exists]r[Exists] which belongs to the set [Exists]R_{ob}[Exists]; I then execute some cognitive actions, and for each such action [Exists]a[Exists] I run my mental model, i.e. perform the transformation [Exists]f_a[Exists] on [Exists]r[Exists]. If this anticipated representation [Exists]f_a(r)[Exists] matches the actual representation [Exists]r'[Exists] after the action [Exists]a[Exists]: [Exists][Exists] f_a(r) = r' [Exists][Exists]
i then my perception of the object [Exists]b[Exists] is confirmed; otherwise I may not be sure about what is going on. Observing a tea-pot I check my actual experience against what I anticipate as the result of the movements of my head and eyeballs. If the two match, I perceive the tea-pot as an object. If I travel in a desert and see on the horizon castles and minarets which disappear or turn topsy-turvy as I get closer, I say that this is a mirage, an illusion, and not a real object. The concept of an object is naturally (one is tempted to say, inevitably) arises in the process of evoluiton. It is simply the first stage in the construction of the world's models. Indeed, since the sense organs of cybernetic animals are constantly moving in the environment, these actions are the first to be modeled. In the huge flow of sensations a line must be drawn between what is the result of the animal's own movements, and other changes which do not depend on the movements, are {sl objective}. Looking for objectivity is nothing else but {sl factoring out certain cognitive actions}. Function [Exists]f_a[Exists] factors out the action [Exists]a[Exists] by predicting what should be observed when the only change in the world is the subject's taking of the action [Exists]a[Exists]. If the prediction comes true, we interpret this as the same kind of stability as when nothing changes at all. The concept of object fixates a certain invariance, or stability, in the perception of a cybernetic system that actively explores its environment. The metasystem transition from representations to their transofrmations is a step towards objectivity of knowledge. Actions and, in particular, sensations are intimately tied to the agent, the subject of knowledge. An object is a transformation and prediction of actions. The very fact that prediction is possible indicates that the transformation depends less on the subject of knowledge, the `I', and more on the `not-I'. This does not ensure a complete objectivity; alas, there is no such thing. But a jump from a representations to a transformation of representations verified by the practice of correct predictions, is the only way we know to increase the informally understood objectivity. When we perceive a tea-pot as an object, we have a lot of cognitive actions to factor out: we can walk around it, grasp it, rotate it in from of our eyes etc. But often we observe things from afar and that is about all we can do, as, fro instance, when we observe a star and still call it an object. Well, from the viewpoint of our theory, we always associate with an object some kind of stability, and stability exist obly with respect to action. In the case of a star, this is the stability with respect to varying conditions of observation. We can observe `the same' star at different times and factor out the differences in time by taking into account the rotation of the sky around the Earth's axis. The same is true with respect to the movement of the observer around the Earth's surface. The more we know of astronomy and physics, the greater number of properties of the object will we discover, such as the constancy of the star's spectrum etc. We also must include into the concept of cognitive actions the more sophisticated and esoteric actions which were not among those actions for which evolution created human brain, but emerge as a result of the development of science. We get involved in this kind of actions when we construct huge accelerators of elementary particles and set up experiments to explore how the particles interact. As an apple and other physical bodies are invariants in the processing of input information by the brain, so an electron and other elementary particles are invariants of the scientific symbolic models of the world. We can measure the charge of the electron in many different ways -- which all are various cognitive actions -- but after making all the computations required by the theory, we still come to the same number (within the error). The same with mass, spin, etc. So an electron is, for us, an object, as real as an apple. One could qualify this statement by noticing that the existence of electrons depends on the legitimacy of our physical theory, which is not absolute. True enough. But who are we to claim that the legitimacy of our brain as a collection of models is absolute? eon
ode{Hierarchical modeling} %part-of: Objective description of the world We defined an object as a family of transformations [Exists]f_a(r)[Exists] on the set of representations which predicts the representation resulting from a given cognitive action [Exists]a[Exists]. This is the same definition as the general definition of a model, where [Exists]f_a[Exists] is the modeling (prediction) function [Exists]M_a[Exists]. The specificity of an object is, first, in the domain of the index [Exists]a[Exists], which is a set of cognitive actions [Exists]A_{cogn}[Exists]; and second, in the way the functions [Exists]f_a[Exists] of the family are further used. The domain [Exists]A_{cogn}[Exists] includes only actions we deem external to the intuitively understood {sl essence} of the object. We call them cognitive because they allow us to separate the object from other phenomena, to see it from different sides -- often literally -- an at the same time not to change the object itself beyond recognition. As for the use of [Exists]f_a[Exists], it serves not to provide a needed prediction, but only to confirm, by checking the prediction against reality, that we do deal with a given object. Then on the basis of this information we, probably, will make a prediction which is needed as such. We see here a hierarchy of two models: a model that, having primary sensory data as input, recognizes an object, and a model which uses this object as input. In order to use a model as an object, it must be {sl objectified}, represented by a material object. This act of representation is of the same nature, and plays the same role as representation in models. In this way a hierarchy of models is constructed, where each next level is a representation of the transformation of the representations of the preceding level. A hierarchical model of this kind is shown in Fig.2. {midinsert smallskip egtt{ setbox1=hbox{[Exists]r^1_{11}[Exists]} setbox2=hbox{[Exists]r^1_{12}[Exists]} setbox3=hbox{[Exists]r^1_{21}[Exists]} setbox4=hbox{[Exists]r^1_{22}[Exists]} setbox5=hbox{[Exists]r^2_{11}[Exists]} setbox6=hbox{[Exists]r^3_{1}[Exists]} setbox7=hbox{[Exists]r^3_{2}[Exists]} setbox8=hbox{[Exists]w'_1[Exists]} setbox9=hbox{[Exists]w_1[Exists]} setbox0=hbox{[Exists]w_2[Exists]} wd1=0in wd2=0in wd3=0in wd4=0in wd5=0in wd6=0in wd7=0in wd8=0in wd9=0in wd0=0in ~ [Exists]M_a[Exists] ~ ~ - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - {f language/conceptions} ~ ox6 ox7 ~ ~ ~ - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - {f brain/perceptions} ~ ox5 ~ ~ ~ - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - {f sense organs/senasations} ~ ox1 ox2 ox3 ox4 ~ [Exists]a'[Exists] [Exists]a[Exists] ~ ~ - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - {f world/action} ~ ox9 ox8 ox0 ~ endtt} medskip centerline{
m Fig.2 Hierarchical modeling scheme} smallskip endinsert}
i It consists of the ground level to be modelled (the world), and three levels of representations. This scheme is constructed by combining several simple modeling schemes shown in Fig.1. On the ground level we see, as in Fig.1, the states [Exists]w_1[Exists] and [Exists]w_2[Exists]; and the ultimate goal of the hierarchy is still to predict some features of [Exists]w_2[Exists] on the basis of the initial state [Exists]w_1[Exists] and the action [Exists]a[Exists]. In Fig.1 these features were expressed in terms of representation of the first level [Exists]r_2[Exists]; in the three-level scheme they are expressed in terms of representation of the third level [Exists]r^3_2[Exists]. Now let us see how the goal of the model is achieved. The representation of [Exists]w_1[Exists] is [Exists]r^1_11[Exists]; this might be, e.g., the image of a tea-pot on the retina of my eye. But I perceive this image as a part of {sl the object} tea-pot. The entire primary modeling scheme is reproduced here: it consists of the states of the world [Exists]w_1[Exists] and [Exists]w_1'[Exists], the cognitive action [Exists]a'[Exists], and the representations [Exists]r^1_{11}[Exists] and [Exists]r^1_{12}[Exists]. Here [Exists]w_1'[Exists] is an intermediate state of the world resulting from the cognitive action [Exists]a'[Exists] (e.g. that of my coming closer to the tea-pot). The transformation of [Exists]r^1_{11}[Exists] into [Exists]r^1_{12}[Exists] is part of my perception of the tea-pot when I make allowance for [Exists]a'[Exists]. The whole scheme of the perception of a tea-pot may be executed any number of times, depending on the time scale of the processes involved; in particular, it is possible that there is no time to check the model property for [Exists]r^1_{12}[Exists], so that the tea-pot will be perceived on the basis of [Exists]r^1_{11}[Exists], which is just a glimpse of it. In any case the transofrmation of [Exists]r^1_{11}[Exists] into [Exists]r^1_{12}[Exists] is objectified as a representation [Exists]r^2_{11}[Exists] on the second level of representations. In a similar manner the other primary models work, which are shown partially in Fig.2. A transformation of [Exists]r^2_{11}[Exists] becomes represented by [Exists]r^3_1[Exists], and the edifice of transformations and representations on the predicted side of the model is constructed analogously. The height of the hierarchy in Fig.2 is three, so on the third level we see the desired prediction [Exists]M_a[Exists]: if [Exists]r^3_1[Exists] and the action [Exists]a[Exists] is taken, then [Exists]r^3_2[Exists]. Iy is very important that representations of the [Exists]i[Exists]-th level are abstractions from {sl transformations} of representations of the [Exists]i-1[Exists]-st level, not from {sl representations themselves}. Indeed, if the representations of higher levels were abstractions of representations of lower levels, then all lower (intermediary) levels of representation would have been unnecessary. Let the representation function of the [Exists]i[Exists]-th level be [Exists]R_i(r_{i-1})[Exists]. Then we could combine the functions of each two neighboring levels into one: [Exists][Exists] R_i(r_{i-2}) = R_i(R_{i-1}(r_{i-2})) [Exists][Exists] Thus a hierarchy of representation levels in this case could have been only a question of expediency; it would not really give any additional power. Repeated abstraction leads to loss of contents, and ultimately to the concept `something', about which we can say nothing. With the hierachical modeling as we describe it, the creation of each new level is a {sl metasystem transition} (see [Tur77]); it provides new possibilities and can be repeated indefinitely. eon
ode{Sensations, perceptions, conceptions} % part-of: Objective description of the world We hypothesize that the hierarchical modeling scheme, as described above, is actually implemented in human brain and produces our many percepitons of objects in the world, where objects may be understood in the widest sense as islands of stability in the see of sensations. We do not know how many levels of this hierarchy is there, and we speak of a hierarchy in a very loose sense. Some models may use models of various lower levels and be used by more than one model of higher levels. We intend the three-level modeling scheme in Fig.2 as a rough picture of human knowledge. The first representation level is constituted by sensations. All levels of the brain hierarchy we compress in one level: that of perceptions. The third level is that of human language and the models we construct in language on the basis of perceptions. Here again we merge many actual levels into one. Sensations are produced by our sense organs. Perceptions are formed and used within the brain. Conceptions are created by ourselves while we create new, linguistic, models of the world. The triad {sl sensation, perception, conception} seems close in meaning to Kant's usage of these terms. We leave it to the reader, though, to judge on it. eon eon
ode{Space} % part-of: Metaphysics Among the most elementary actions known to us are small displacements ``in space''. We have put it in the quotes, because people have accustomed to imagine that some entity, called ``space'' exists as a primary reality, which creates the possibility of moving from one point of this space to another. Our analysis turns this notion topsy-turvy. Only actions constitute observable reality; space is nothing but a product of our imagination which we construct from small displacements, or shifts, of even smaller objects called points. If [Exists]x[Exists] is such a shift, then [Exists]xx[Exists] -- the action [Exists]x[Exists] repeated twice -- is a double shift, which we would call in our conventional wisdom a shift at the double distance in the same direction. On the other hand, we may want to represent a shift [Exists]x[Exists] as the result of another shift [Exists]x'[Exists] repeated twice: [Exists]x = x'x'[Exists]. It so happens that we can make three different kinds of shifts, call them [Exists]x, y, z[Exists], none of which can be reduced to a combination of the other two. At the same time any shift [Exists]w[Exists] can be reduced to a properly chosen combination of shifts [Exists]x, y, z[Exists]. So we say that our space has three dimensions. eon
ode{Time} % part-of: Metaphysics When we do nothing for a while we still feel that something has happened: we say that some ``time'' has pas sed. In terms of actions, doing nothing is a special type of action. If we denote it by [Exists]t[Exists], then [Exists]tt[Exists] is an action of waiting for two times longer than with [Exists]t[Exists]. We often say that all real processes take place in space and time. The meaning of such statements is that in addition to what really goes on, we imagine some reference actions of consecutive shifts (``in space'') and waits (``in time'') and esatblish relationships between these actions and actual objects and processes. Thus, in accordance with Kant's view, space and time are not observable realities, but our ways to organize experience. When we think about space, we treat those shifts which create the space as instantaneous. In fact, however, all actions have a time component. Space, as we understand it intuitively, is a complete abstraction from time. Respectively, our intuitive time is abstracted form space and from everything that happens in space. This intuition, when formalized into a theory, gave rise to classical mechanics. It treats time as sort of a flow which goes on uniformly in every point of space. If the ultimate reality is that of actions, then there must be as many times as there are agents. When an agent acts, the time that elapses is just one of the characteristics of the action. Thus whatever is happening, there must be its own time measure for it. This truth was dramatically demonstrated by Einstein's relativity theory. When we measure time, we take some repetitious process, like the swinging of a pendulum, for a model of other processes. We may say, for instance, that John needes 80 `pendulums' of time to smoke up a cigarette. In terms of the modelling scheme (Fig.1), the state when John is lighting his cigarette is [Exists]w_1[Exists]; the state when he extinguishes it is [Exists]w_2[Exists]; the representation function [Exists]R[Exists] is registration of the current value of the counter; [Exists]r_1[Exists] and [Exists]r_2[Exists] are the states of the counter at the beginning and end of smoking.
ode{Objectification} % part-of: Time We often want to think and speak about an action or process as something definite, constant -- in other words, as an object. Then we {sl objectify} it, i.e. replace the process, in reality or in our imagination, by an object. Objectification is a kind of metasystem transition: a process becomes an object to be manipulated by a metasystem. Strictly speaking, we should say `becomes represented by an object', but `becomes an object' is also admissible, because as a rule the representation would be such as to allow to reproduce the process, maybe even with variations. Hence a partial equivalence between a process and its objectification. One common case of objectification is replacement of a process by its definition. For instance, we define algorithms as computational processes which we expect to be executed in a certain fixed manner. The definition of an algorithmic process is an object, usually a text in some formal language. The semantics, i.e. the meaning, of the language is provided by a machine which executes the process in accordance with its definition. The famous Turing machine is an example. The mapping of an action onto its representation, which is made in the use of a model, is also a form of objectification: representations are objects. eon
ode{Historical record} % part-of: Time Consdier a model [Exists]M[Exists] in which certain states of the world [Exists]w_1[Exists] and [Exists]w_2[Exists] are represented, respectively, by [Exists]r_1[Exists] and [Exists]r_2[Exists]. Recall that states of (a part of) the world are, in fact, {sl cognitive actions} used by [Exists]M[Exists] to create representations of the world. Since [Exists]w_1[Exists] and [Exists]w_2[Exists] are actions, we can ask ourselves: how will [Exists]M[Exists] represent the composite action [Exists]w_1 w_2[Exists]? Typically, each model would have a certain set, a tool-bag of ``atomic'' actions to register the states of the world. Therefore, to represent the sequential composition of those, a method must either exist in [Exists]M[Exists], or to be built as an addition to [Exists]M[Exists]. Depending on the physical nature of the representations [Exists]r_i[Exists], various methods may be used; for example, if [Exists]r_i[Exists] are symbols we can simply concatenate them: [Exists]r_1 r_2[Exists]; then a sequence of state-registering actions [Exists]w_1, w_2, ldots, w_n[Exists] will be represented as [Exists]r_1, r_2, ldots, r_n[Exists]. No matter what the actual method of combining representations is, we can think of the result as a sequence of representations. We shall refer to it as a {sl historical record}.
ode{Memory} % part-of: Historical record The subsystem of the subject of knowledge which keeps historical records is its {sl memory}. eon Historical records add nothing to our formal concepts of model and knowledge. States are always actions, whether they are split into sequences or not. It is a technical detail, after all. I can consider every state of the world in my knowledge as a sequence of actions [Exists]w_1, w_2, ldots, w_n[Exists] which covers all my life from the moment I was born. Then my predictions will always be functions of the representation [Exists]r_1, r_2, ldots, r_n[Exists] . This, of course, does not exclude predictions which take into account only the latest member [Exists]r_n[Exists] of the sequence. If the system has memory, then memory becomes a component of each current representation; its role in predicting, though, may vary in wide limits.
ode{Present, Past, Future} % part-of: Historical record The last atomic representation at the moment of making a prediction is referred to as {sl the present}. The whole sequence of memorized representation, the total historic record, is {sl the past}. The representation resulting from prediction is {sl the future}. It is clear from this definition that the duration of time which is included in the present depends on the cognitive actions which determine the state of the world. In the context of writing a diary, the current day is the present. In the work of a computer, one millionth of a second may mean a long past state of affairs. eon
ode{Real time vs. model time} % part-of: Time Henri Bergson was first to notice and emphasize the difference between {sl real time}, in which we live and act, and the objectified time of history and physics. Imagine a pendulum which at each swing puts a mark on a moving tape. We have a historical record of `how the time is moving'. This historic record is an object at every moment we look at it. We use it as a model of reality. We shall refer to the marks on the tape as representing a {sl model time}. It is very much different from the real time. Real time is such that two moments of it never coexist. In model time the moments coexist as different objects in some space. Thus Bergson calls model time a projection of real time on space. Bergson's real time is irreversible. Model time is reversible: we read historical records equally well from left to right and right to left. The seemingly inconceivable feature of Feynman's diagrams, the movement of a particle in the direction opposite to time, is explained simply by the fact that the time of physical theories is model time, i.e. a spacial phenomenon. The solution of the fundamental metaphysical problem is the key to the understanding of time. As long as you see the world as abiding, at each moment of time, in a certain state, your time will be reversible, because there always remains the possibility of returning to one of the passed states. You may invent some tricks to prevent such things from happening in your theory, but a theory which requires patches at the very base is seriously deficient. If, on the contrary, the only reality of the world is action, then time is irreversible from the beginning, because a new action does not revoke a previous action, as a new state does, but builds on it. If in the sequence of two alternating states [Exists]w_1w_2w_1w_2w_1w_2ldots [Exists] etc. [Exists]w_1[Exists] and [Exists]w_2[Exists] are understood, literally, as states of the world, then each time a state returns, the world is the same, as if the time were running on and back. If the states are cognitive actions, the reality is continuously changing: [Exists][Exists] w_1, w_1w_2, w_1w_2w_1, w_1w_2w_1w_2, w_1w_2w_1w_2w_1 ldots [Exists][Exists]
i There is no return. Action is cumulative. In the contemporary science, real time shows up in probability t heory and its applications, such as statistical physics. Probability is a characterization of certain actions, not states. In the theory of probability we deal with acts of choosing of a number of possibilities. If there are ten possible actions then the probability of actually doing one of them is [Exists]10_{-1}[Exists]. If in the second step there is again the same number of options, the probability of the composition is [Exists]10_{-2}[Exists]. Suppose that the first step was from state [Exists]w_1[Exists] to [Exists]w_2[Exists], and the second step takes the system back to [Exists]w_1[Exists]. The probability of each choice in one more step will be [Exists]10_{-3}[Exists], not [Exists]10_{-1}[Exists]. In the next step it will be [Exists]10_{-4}[Exists] etc. It is cumulative; there is no way back. This is why the time of statistical physics is irreversible. In the world where the ultimate reality is action, time differs very much from the time of classical mechanics. The former is irreversible, the latter reversible: we can designate this difference as a difference in macro-structure. There is even a greater difference in micro-structure. Our real time is closer to Bergson's {sl duration} than to mechanical infinitely divisible time. Unlike the mechanical (model) time, real time is quantized: a quantum of time is the time involved in one action. An elementary action has a duration within which it makes no sense to speak about distinct moments of time. Real time does not consist of a continuum of infinitely small time coordinates. To make small times real, corresponding actions must exist. As it happens, this is not quite simple. We know from physics that there is no universal quantum of time; time quanta depend on actions. To perform an action with the duration [Exists]t[Exists] (by the order of magnitude), we must involve an amount of energy [Exists]h/t[Exists], so the _expression `a point in time', which presumes a duration of [Exists]t = 0[Exists], presumes an infinite energy. If it has any meaning, then, possibly, only for the state of the world just before the big bang. eon eon
ode{Individual physical body} %part-of: Metaphysics We saw that an object is more than just a complex of sensations: it includes a certain measure of stability with regards of our cognitive actions. When we speak of a physical body we have in mind more than just an object. We include the object's {sl historical record}. Hence `a cat' is an abstraction applicable to any cat. The pet cat I may have at home is an on-going historic record of my having it. The historic record of a physical body may not be actually known in full, not even partially. The important thing is that to speak of a physical body we must associate some, may be abstract, historical record with our direct perception of it. This record makes physical bodies, in principle, {sl identifiable}. Thus we consdier the terms `identifiable' or `individual' body or object as synonimous with `physical' body. One of the most beautiful features of quantum mechanics is the way a philosophical analysis is translated into theory and experimentally confirmed. We can speak of individual physical bodies only if we can actually identify them by some means. We cannot do that to elementary particles when there are no impenetrable boundaries between them. Therefore they must be considered indistinguishable. This requires symmetrization of the wave function, which leads to various physical consequences brilliantly confirmed by experiment. Electrons are not physical bodies in the usual sense, because they are not individually identifiable bodies. eon
ode{Causality} % part-of: Metaphysics Let us analyze the meaning of the statements of the form: `[Exists]C[Exists] is the cause of the effect [Exists]E[Exists]', or simply `[Exists]C[Exists] causes [Exists]E[Exists]'. Here [Exists]C[Exists] is an action, and [Exists]E[Exists] a state of the world. Sometimes we speak of the cause [Exists]C[Exists] as a state too, but what we mean then is that this state leads inescapably to a certain action which causes [Exists]E[Exists]. On other occasions, we speak of the effect [Exists]E[Exists] as an action, but this, again, for the same reason that this action is an immediate result of the situation caused by [Exists]C[Exists]. So, in the mainstream, the cuase is an action, and the effect a state of affairs. One could try to explain the meaning of causality by saying that whenever [Exists]C[Exists] takes place, [Exists]E[Exists] follows. But this is not a satisfactory explanation. We see that after a day a night always comes, but the day is not the cause of the night; the cause is rather the rotation of the Earth. A simple observation of the sequence [Exists](C,E)[Exists] is not sufficient. [Exists]C[Exists] and [Exists]E[Exists] might be two effects of a common cause, or this could be just a coincidence. It was noted by many thinkers that causal relation is more than just sequence in time. In search of the true meaning of causality consider the case when the cause [Exists]C[Exists] is {sl my own} action. By `my own' we mean, as usually, a reference to the subject of knowledge. So, `if I perform [Exists]C[Exists], there will be [Exists]E[Exists]'. Our interpretation of this statement is the pair of predictions [Exists]A[Exists] and [Exists]B[Exists] in Fig.3. {midinsert smallskip egtt{ ~ ~ True True True False ~ -{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}- -{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}- ~ | | | | ~ | | | | ~ S| E| S| E| ~ | | | | ~ | C | | do nothing | ~ -{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-} -{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}- ~ (A) (B) endtt} medskip centerline{
m Fig.3 Two predictions involved in causal relationship} centerline{
m when the agent is the subject of knowledge } endinsert} smallskip
i In words: if a situation recognized by abstraction [Exists]S[Exists] holds, and I do action [Exists]C[Exists], then a situation characterized by abstraction [Exists]E[Exists] takes place. But if in the same situation I do nothing, then [Exists]E[Exists] does not occur. This precisely matches our intuitive understanding of causality. Now suppose that [Exists]C[Exists] is not my action, but that of some other agent. It may come as a surprize that this, seemingly innocuous, substitution radically changes the picture. We must remember that I can perceive an action directly only when it is my own action; all other actions I perceive only as representations created by my sense organs. Therefore, the action [Exists]C[Exists] must now be a part of the initial situation S. Let this complex situation be represented as [Exists]S+obs(C)[Exists], where [Exists]obs(C)[Exists] stands for the fact that I observe [Exists]C[Exists]. Suppose we try to express the meaning of causality in this case as consisting of the pair of predictions in Fig.4. {midinsert smallskip egtt{ setbox4=hbox{[Exists]S+obs(C)[Exists]} wd4 = 0in ~ True True True False ~ -{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}- -{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{ ~ | | | | ~ | | | | ~ox4 | E| S| E| ~ | | | | ~ | do nothing | | do nothing | ~ -{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}- -{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{ ~ (A) (B) ~ medskip centerline{
m Fig.4 A wrong interpretation of causal relationship} } endinsert} smallskip One can see that this is not a correct _expression of causality. This is only an observation of time sequences, which we have rejected above. It could be that there exists a real cause [Exists]C'[Exists] which first causes action [Exists]C[Exists], and then situation [Exists]E[Exists]. For example, I can, on some days, have scrambled eggs for breakfast. On such days I break two eggs and fry the content in a frying-pan. An external observer will see that when I break eggs, I always fry them; when I do not break eggs, I do not fry them. This is an if-then relationship, and it can be a useful model of my uninterrupted breakfast. But it would be an error to conclude that breaking eggs is the {sl cause} of frying them. Then is there any meaning in speaking about a cause which is not an action of the subject of knowledge? We believe, there is, but it is a result of a certain {sl reduction} of this case to the basic case where the cause [Exists]C[Exists] is the subject's action. There is an additional element introduced by the subject of knowledge in understanding causality in the case of sombody's else action. It is a tacit assumption that I could, somehow, allow or prevent the action of which I think as a cause. The interpretation of the statement that an action [Exists]C[Exists] of some agent causes [Exists]E[Exists] as the statement that if I, the subject of knowledge, {sl allow} [Exists]C[Exists] to take place, then [Exists]E[Exists] ensues; however, if I somehow {sl prevent} it, there will be no [Exists]E[Exists]. This view of causality is pres ented in Fig.5. {midinsert smallskip egtt{ ~ ~ True True True False ~ -{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}- -{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}- ~ | | | | ~ | | | | ~ S| E| S| E| ~ | | | | ~ | allow C | | prevent C | ~ -{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}- -{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}-{-}- ~ (A) (B) ~ medskip centerline{
m Fig.5 Two predictions involved in causal relationship} centerline{
m when the agent is not the subject of knowledge } } endinsert} smallskip The actual feasibility of my preventing an action is no issue. The meaning of my statements is that they provide certain models of the world. It is not necessary that every model be directly verifiable. Some models (metamodels) help create other models, which produce directly verifiable predictions. When I say that rotation of the Earth is the cause of alternation of day and night, the meaning of it is, according to our scheme, that if I stop the rotation of the Earth, the effect of alternation will disappear. Clearly, I cannot stop the Earth from rotationg, but this does not make the statement less true or useful. When I think of the rotation of the Earth, I actually have in mind a model of the Solar system, where celestial bodies are represented by balls of appropriate (and convenient for my imagination) sizes. In this model I can actually stop the Earth's rotation and see what happens. This is the true meaning of our causal relationship. Since a model of a model is a model, we often do not care to make distinction between our models and our models of models. As required by our epistemology, we explained causal statements as certain models of the world. We might now ask: what about the concept of model itself? Does it not include the idea of causality? The answer is: yes, it does. In the use of models causality is exploited twice. First, whenever we run the machinery of the model, we expect that the switching on of the model produce a definite effect. Second, when we compare our predictions with the reality, we expect them to match. The fact that there are such phenomena as models of the world is, essentially, the same fact as the existence of causality.
ode{Laws of nature} % part-of: Causality The laws of nature are models of the world with a wide range of applicability. Predictions we make using models, in particular, laws of nature, are expressed in terms of representation functions, or abstractions. Abstractions are many-to-one mappings. There are always more than one state of the world that are compatible with prediction. The prediction of a representation [Exists]r[Exists] is the restriction of the expected states of the world to those states [Exists]w[Exists] which are mapped on [Exists]r[Exists] by the representation function [Exists]R[Exists]: [Exists]R(w) = r[Exists]. The mechanistic worldview saw the laws of nature as something that uniquely prescribes how events should develop, with indeterminacy resulting only from our lack of knowledge; for contemporary science the laws of nature are only restrictions imposed on a basically non-deterministic world. It is not an accident that the most general laws of nature are conservation laws, which do not prescribe how things must be, but only put certain restrictions on them. eon eon
ode{Number} % part-of: Metaphysics The {sl number} is a conceptual scheme, an abstraction of the second level from {sl specific numbers}: 1, 2, 3, ... etc. The abstraction procedure to recognize specific numbers is {sl counting}. Counting is based on the ability to divide the surrounding world into distinct objects. This ability emerged quite far back in the course of evolution; the vertebrates appear to have it in the same degree as humans do. The use of specific numbers is a natural integrated description complementary to the differential description by recognizing distinct objects. This ability would certainly be advantageous for higher animals in the struggle for existence. And cybernetic apparatus for counting could be very simple -- incomparably simpler than for recognition of separate objects in pictures. Yet nature, for some reason, did not give our brain this ability. The numbers we can directly recognize are ridiculously small, up to five or six at best (though it can be somewhat extended by training). Thus the number 2 is a neuronal concept, but 20 and 200 are not. We can use them only through counting, creating artificial representqations in the material external to the brain. The material may be, and was historically, fingers and toes, then pebbles, notches etc., and finally sophisticated signes on paper and electronic states of computer circuitry. For theoretical purposes the best is still the ancient-style representation where a chosen symbol, say {f 1} stands for one object. Thus 2 is {f 11}, and 5 is {f 11111}. This is referred to as the {sl unary} representation of numbers. eon
ode{Infinity} % part-of: Metaphysics In mathematics and philosophy we find two concepts of infinity: {sl potential infinity}, which is the infinity of a process which never stops, and {sl actual infinity} which is supposed to be static and completed, so that it can be thought of as an object.
ode{Potential infinity} % part-of: Infinity The cybernetic philosopy readily embraces the concept of potential infinity; in fact, it is hard to see how we can avoid it. We say that a process {sl ends} when it reaches a certain stage. In a particular case, we can define the end stage so that it never takes place. As every general notion, this is an abstraction: we have abstracted from the practical impossibilty to run any real process infinitely, and in fact, for very long. In this abstraction, no matter how long we have run the process, we always can do, or observe, the next step. This is why this infinity is called potential. At every specific stage the process involves no more than quite a finite reality; it is infinite only potentially. eon
ode{Actual infinity} % part-of: Infinity For {sl actual infinity}, which is thought of as static and completed, we have no place in our system of concepts. On the intuitive level, we cannot imagine anything that would qualify as actual infinity, because neither we, nor our evolutionary predecessors ever had anything like that in experience. When we try to imagine something infinite, e.g., infinite space, we actually imagine a process of moving from point to point without any end in sight. This is potential, not actual, infinity. On a more formal level we can demonstrate the incompatibility of the concept of actual infinity with our cybernetic understanding of meaning. Indeed, suppose that some abstraction [Exists]r[Exists] represents the concept of an infinite object, and we use it while constructing a model. According to our semantics, there must exist a representation function [Exists]R[Exists] which recognizes whether a given state of the world belongs to this concept, an if so, results in [Exists]r[Exists]. Moreover, the function [Exists]R[Exists] must, by definition, always require a finite time for coming up with a definite result. If the ``infinite'' object can be always recognized as such in a finite number of steps, it is not actually infinite, because it can be adequately replaced by a finite object. If, in accordance with the intuitive concept of an infinite object, its recognition may require infinite time, then the representation function will have to work, at least in some cases, infinitely, but then it is not a valid representation function. Thus we cannot use the concept of actual infinity at all. eon As an example, consider the process of counting. We can imagine it going on infinitely if we do not count real sheep or apples, but simply produce consecutive numbers. Let us represent numbers in the unary system; then the process is: centerline{ {f 1}, {f 11}, {f 111}, ... etc. {sl infinitely} } When we say that this process is infinite, we mean that whatever is the current number, we can add one more {f 1} to it. Thus we deal with potential infinity. To convert it into an actual infinity, we must imagine an object that includes in itself all whole numbers. We call it the set of all positive whole numbers. Suppose that such a thing exists. How would it be possible for an abstr action function [Exists]R[Exists] to distinguish it from other objects, e.g. from the set of all whole numbers with the exception of the number [Exists]10^{50}[Exists]? Intuitively, [Exists]R[Exists] must examine the infinite number of the elements of the set. Since this is impossible to achieve in any finite time, the needed function [Exists]R[Exists] does not exist. What we can do, however, is to create an {sl objectification} of the process which generates all whole numbers. A machine which initiates this process (and, of course, never stops) is such an objectification. This machine is a finite object. It can be made of metal, with an electric motor as the agent causing the process of work. Or we can describe it in some language addressing a human agent, but requirung only simple ``mechanical'' actions uniquely defined at each stage of the process. Such descriptions are known as {sl algorithms}. If we use the English language for writing algorithms, this machine, to be referred to as [Exists]N[Exists], could be as follows: medskip {sl At the initial stage of the process produce the number {f 1}. At each next stage take the number produced at the preceding stage and produce the number obtained by putting {f 1} on the right side of it.'' } medskip Now we can say that the set of whole numbers {sl is} [Exists]N[Exists]. We have no objections against sets defined in this way. Their meaning is crystal clear. Their infinity is still potential. The problem with contemporary mathematics is that many sets it operates with {sl cannot} be represented by finite mechanical generators. They are {sl uncountable}. The question of the nature and meaning of these sets is, in the eyes of contemporary mathemticians and philosophers, wide open. Yet their usefulness is abundantly demonstrated. If there were no way to interpret uncountable sets in our philosophy, it would undermine our claim that the basic principles on which we build our philosophy are universally applicable and sufficient. Fortunately, we {sl can} interpret set theory, as well as classical and intuitionist logic, in our terms (see [Tur87]). Our interpretation assigns quite definite {sl meanings}, in our sense of the word, to the basic concepts of logic and set theory, and does it without any recourse to the concept of actual infinity. eon
ode{God} % part-of: Metaphysics In a philosophy where the basis of existence is actions and agents, the concept of God is naturally introduced. We observe a lot of hierarchical relations between agents. The scope of one ``rank-and-file'' act of electron scattering is very small. In comparison, my decisions {sl control}, i.e. change conditions for, a great deal of processes in the tissues of my body, down to elementary subatomic interactions. God may be understood as the agent on the highest level of the control hierarchy in the world. What my mind is for my body, God is for the whole of the Universe. This definition, of course, is not a proof of existence. We can develop both theistic and atheistic versions of cybernetic metaphysics. In the atheistic version the accent is made on the concept of self-organization of matter. According to this view, the control hierarchies of the world grow up from the bottom, so that nothing is over them, no agent constructs the hierarchies from above. According to the theistic conception the creation of the Universe was the starting act of God. The laws of nature are manifestations of God's will, which also directs the universal evolution of the world. The fate of a metaphysical theory is decided when it leads to verifiable predictions, or at least a widely accepted scientific theory. Nobody has yet derived a scientific theory from the existence of God. But to prove that there is no God, it is not sufficient to develop theories which work without God; it is necessary to derive predictions from the {sl non-existence} of God. This has not yet been done either. So we shall do our best if we watch developments along both theistic and atheistic lines of thought.


COMMENTS

-



 

devils sperm

14:19 Nov 17 2005
Times Read: 561


The sun is blareing outside.all the shades are pulld shut,but that isnt doing the job of shuting all the light out.but anyway.to the point in this i am to write.sipping my coffee i had such a random thought that was soo unlike me.i couldnt stop laffing at myself.it is truely my innner self amuzing my own mind. ok i will tell.. picture this. a sperm cell raceing to be the first in line.but this is no ordinary cell, this cell is red and has lil fings unfolding a perfect smile,with a firery tail chaseing along. that is about it, i found it very funny.im sure he could have lilhorns too.


COMMENTS

-



 

tea

19:02 Nov 16 2005
Times Read: 562


I have made the perfect tea today.

composed of linden flowers

,orangeblossoms,chamomile,passion flowers,valerian root and a hint of lavender flowers.

i must say, it is almost intoxicating to me.

this would be the perfect after sex tea, or maybe even with a shot of absy,,


COMMENTS

-



 

love+Evil

03:28 Nov 16 2005
Times Read: 565


you know when someone says that it is better to love and lost thean not to love at all.this is not true for me. i have so much love flowing from me that it hurts.i dont understand why or even how i came to be like this.i still have the grotest side of my mind working all the same as ever.i could say hello to some stranger and almost instantly find some thing to love about he/she.i find love even in evil.pure Evil is mostly made up of twisted love in one from or anouther.

at one hand i feel as if i enjoy the love all around.at the outher i do nothing but damm it.

why should one has so mush to give and no room to receiv it.being alone is nothing but a well sought after task everyday.achived most of the time.Self pitty is a amuseing feeling.my gratest love is one of the oldest sins.

tell me.if love is all that is good,why do the evil have it?anyone, please tell me.


COMMENTS

-



 

random

18:07 Nov 15 2005
Times Read: 566


lost but not forgoten, i dont know the reasonning of this thought. the point on dwelling on such a thing is hurtfull to my soul.my sould hurts allways for you and him.the way i was touch,the wet love that came about from feelings of the sin that was bestowd to me.I morn the loss of the times.


COMMENTS

-



 

random

15:16 Nov 15 2005
Times Read: 572


i awoke todayday with a pain in my eyes. like they were being push on by some cold metal object of that purpose.the sun is bright and hellbent on anying me.all i can think abou tis the jar of pot that sits in the head.my coffee is my savior.

sometimes i wish to shave my head bald.i hate how this mop ist toying with my punished eyes.

now why should this morning be unlike anyouther.i should go out into the sun and get it over with,cuss god and belittle all that he has done. on with the day! i miss you.


COMMENTS

-



 

MISSING YOU

03:11 Nov 15 2005
Times Read: 573


The eavning moon is bright and silver. and im stoned.

what more could i want. I WANT YOU!

i miss haveing you by myside. if there was a chance or a small remote possability to be with you, i would not hesitate to end it all. your hair use to tickle my nose when we kissd. you lips gave me a purpose.but now. i can even remember what you lookd like.sometimes i beleav that i am being punishd by a god or something.my heart is slow to heal,still.

it is hard to think of anytype of fueture now, the is no light at anytunnle no silver lineing,nothering but the sarrow wich has hunted me for so long now.

where is my love,,is she up there,down there, or somewhere eles,i so pray out to what ever it may be to,,to be gental with her..she is soft and careing.hold her close to you and tell her you love her.


COMMENTS

-



 

random

20:10 Nov 12 2005
Times Read: 577


ok, maybe today isnt going that good... i hate the fuckin daylight.. i took a walk to see the carcus that i feel beside...it was only half a carcus... looked cool, but had a new stench of death.. i could tell that a gator got it.. i dont like to see meaningless death.. but im not going to eat it.. maybe use it as bait... im almost out of beer tooo...now im trying to get the thoughts of myself out of my own head.i suck if you dont know. really.

who need atention,, not me.. i dont want it..

whos a freak.. not me.. it is my thoughts that the man in the suite is the freak.. he askd me for bud. he ask me who she was.. then he asked me for my phone number.. wtf.

now i have this kid buggin me about the shit.. im not a dealler.. i dont even smoke that much..i dont even have any now...

ok i need some angry sex. i need it BAD!....


COMMENTS

-



 

random .

14:58 Nov 12 2005
Times Read: 578


it seems that today is going to be a good one also..i awoke with a beer in hand. does anyone eles sleep walk?i was danceing with thegreen monster lastnight and feel in a ditch. the was a flamingo carcus beside me.. pink realy is a good color in the moon light. it didnt smelll that bad either. but anyway.that was last nigh this is today.sooo i got the beer and now i need a lil something eles..a joint would be nice, but i gave it up. i think im going to go outside and anoy the golfers as they go by..this is my fav. past time..what a waste of land huh. yes that sounds good to me. i just realized something...i love this site. and if your reading me,, i love you tooo...


COMMENTS

-



 

random thoughts.

15:08 Nov 10 2005
Times Read: 580


Today is a good day.I am going to start drinking early,lol. for those of you who dont know me.. i allways drink on a good day.

i have a taste in my mouth right now and i cant describe it. it is sweet,but yet bitter.kinda like

a strawberry orange...sounds good huh...well it is.. i dont have to much to say right now.. i dont speak much when i am content..sooo for all of you who arent have a day as good as mine....hahahaha fuck you! in a nice way.-cyas


COMMENTS

-



 

you asked..!

20:45 Nov 04 2005
Times Read: 582


ok you asked for it, so whey do you want to know so much,,, are you something special, something out of the ordinary. ok, i get it. your one of them.. a freakin leach,,thats what we call you..or ateast they call you.

After haveing several conversations with a few of you it seem that there is much to tell. After all you ask for it.sooo where do we begain, you wanted to know how it felt to have your body die. well its not jsut your body dieing, it is also giving birth to its self in a way. ok the only way i can put it into a physical feeling for you is this.. you have to consider the poisoning of the blood stream and the emplodeing of useless organs...ok here we go.. first off. run a hot shower about as hot as you can stand it.. don't get in slow...jumping all at once.. this is how it feels to have the black blood roll in. and for the organs... hmm...come closer and let me show you.So if there is anything eles i may help with please i am at your beckon calll..


COMMENTS

-






COMPANY
REQUEST HELP
CONTACT US
SITEMAP
REPORT A BUG
UPDATES
LEGAL
TERMS OF SERVICE
PRIVACY POLICY
DMCA POLICY
REAL VAMPIRES LOVE VAMPIRE RAVE
© 2004 - 2025 Vampire Rave
All Rights Reserved.
Vampire Rave is a member of 
Page generated in 0.5606 seconds.
X
Username:

Password:
I agree to Vampire Rave's Privacy Policy.
I agree to Vampire Rave's Terms of Service.
I agree to Vampire Rave's DMCA Policy.
I agree to Vampire Rave's use of Cookies.
•  SIGN UP •  GET PASSWORD •  GET USERNAME  •
X